A function from to
is called even if for all
,
. We might call it even about the point
if, for all
,
.
Conversely, we can call a function strongly non-even if for all ,
,
.
Finding strongly non-even functions is easy, as any injective function provides a trivial example. We can make things harder for ourselves by considering only functions from to
. But now, it is just as easy to show that there are no strongly non-even functions.
Therefore, let’s make the following definition: Let a function be non-even of order
if, for all
,
. Thus, a strongly non-even function is non-even of order
, and a function being non-even of order
implies that it’s non-even of order
for all
.
In this paper, the set theorists Peter Komjáth and Saharon Shelah proved:
The existence of a non-even function of order 1 is equivalent to the Continuum Hypothesis (i.e., the statement that
).
Thus, if we assume that there is a non-even function of order 1, then we can conclude that . Can we weaken the hypothesis and still conclude something interesting? We can, as they also proved:
For any
, if there is a non-even function of order
, then
.
They showed this by showing the following (the statement above follows directly from this, given just a bit of thought):
For any vector space
over
of cardinality
, and any function
from
to
, there is an
and a set
of unordered pairs
such that
and
, where the cardinality of
is
.
I’ll show here how to prove the weaker statement obtained by replacing with
.
Fix and
. We will construct a set of basis elements
with the property that for every set
,
. Taking
to be
, this will provide the required number
of unordered pairs. (As a slight bit of notational convenience, if
is a set of basis elements, I will write
for
.)
Let be a basis for
. For
, let
be called the
th slice of basis elements. For each
between
and
and
, we will pick
to be in the
th slice of basis elements.
Given , suppose that we have defined
for
and we will define
as follows: pick it so that it is in the
th slice of basis elements but is not any singleton set of the form:
for any finite sets
and
. Since there are only
such singleton sets, and
elements of the
th slice of basis elements, we can find such a
.
Now we define the . Given
, assume that
have already been defined and we will define
: pick it from the
th slice so that for all subsets
of
,
(this is possible by the defining condition of
.
It is now easy to prove the following proposition by induction on :
For any set
(where
),
equals
.
(The proof simply uses the defining property of the .) Now, taking
, the result follows.
That’s a fun construction! It’s always neat to have a result where the cardinality
actually means something about something in some way n dimensional.
But not having looked at the Komjáth and Shelah paper, does this tell us anything interesting and new about these cardinalities? These strongly non-even functions seem sort of silly as a sort of non-symmetry, since they just are the injections, while being non-even of order n feels a bit more meaningful, but perhaps too complicated to be intuitively interesting. Is there any motivation for considering these non-symmetric functions beyond the connection to the continuum?
The couple of places that I’ve seen these functions come up have been in the context of the study of symmetrically continuous functions, which is defined to be true of
at
if
, but I’ve only seen those discussed in the context of the set theory of the real line.
However, that probably says more about my lack of breadth of knowledge than it does about the applications of the context. I’ve seen the book “Symmetric Properties of real functions” referenced as a analytical basis for studying these types of things, and you can see a preview at:
http://books.google.com/books?id=BMWk0X8rl_YC&lpg=PP1&ots=SF0LuDF6P8&dq=thomson%20symmetric%20properties%20of%20real%20functions&pg=PR11
In any case, I could easily be wrong, but as far as I know, this result is only entertainment; I don’t know that it tells anything fundamentally new either about cardinalities or real functions.
That notion of symmetric continuity sounds fun too, though I don’t know what a non-logician would make of it. Anyway, it still sounds like fun stuff, even if mainly recreational.
This is a very cool post.
thanks
Just because ℝ is too big?